The Relationship between Philosophy and Theology in the Postmodern Age [Electronic resources] نسخه متنی

اینجــــا یک کتابخانه دیجیتالی است

با بیش از 100000 منبع الکترونیکی رایگان به زبان فارسی ، عربی و انگلیسی

The Relationship between Philosophy and Theology in the Postmodern Age [Electronic resources] - نسخه متنی

Muhammad Legenhausen

| نمايش فراداده ، افزودن یک نقد و بررسی
افزودن به کتابخانه شخصی
ارسال به دوستان
جستجو در متن کتاب
بیشتر
تنظیمات قلم

فونت

اندازه قلم

+ - پیش فرض

حالت نمایش

روز نیمروز شب
جستجو در لغت نامه
بیشتر
لیست موضوعات
توضیحات
افزودن یادداشت جدید




on many Christian theologians. [28]


The philosophy of religion as practiced by Christian
philosophers with training in analytic philosophy may be understood as a
movement which to a large extent is diametrically opposed to
postmodernism. To the postmodemists, the Christian philosophers seem a bit
naive-still arguing about how to defend the rationality of asserting the
truth of various religious doctrines. To the philosopher, however, what
room remains for religion in the confines of postmodernism is little more
than a sentimental attachment to the symbols and rituals of religion shorn
of the metaphysical or transcendent significance which gives them their
power and is responsible for the strong emotional response they provoke in
the first place.


This is a claim. I suspect that most of my readers will
agree with it, and that we do not have to look very far to find arguments
to back it up. The claim is that the strength of the hold on the human
imagination exerted by religion as evidenced by phenomena as diverse as
the Islamic Revolution in Iran and allusions to religious themes in
contemporary American fiction depends on the fact that religions allege
that they contain truths that are absolute, truths that go beyond the
particularities of their expressions in various cultural contexts. The
questions of whether or not this allegation is correct, and whether it is
even rational to believe it, are central to contemporary discussions of
the philosophy of religion.


For this reason alone, the skepticism of the
postmodernist is important and requires a response. But aside from how
this response is formulated, there is this other question of whether
postmodernism can provide a philosophical perspective from which theology
is more profoundly understood or whether it undermines theology by denying
that it has any real connection with Ultimate Reality The Christian
postmodemists and many, if not the majority, of contemporary Christian
theologians contend that the question of the truth of religious doctrine
can be dismissed without damage to religion, at least without damage to
Protestant Christianity, because the focus of the evangelical's religion
is salvation rather than gnosis.


This contention is dubious for several reasons. First,
because the vast majority of believers, past and present, of the world's
religions have understood their religions as making important claims about
reality. Any denial of the importance of religious truth is a distortion
of religious thought. Second, in Islam and Christianity, the Ultimate
Reality is known as God, and the practical, symbolic and social dimensions
of religious life are directed toward obedience and worship of God as the
means to salvation. If claims that God exists are dismissed as naive, then
the doubts generated about the reality of the object of worship threaten
to make the meaningfulness of worship doubtful.


Without God, worship is pointless, and without
meaningful worship, there is no salvation. Third, the aura of the sacred
and feelings of holiness generated by religion seem to involve the idea
that the sacred provides us with a vehicle by means of which the mundane
is to be transcended, the merely perspectival is to be escaped. In
revealed religion, particular historical events are designated as
revelation, and with this designation Christians and Muslims cease to see
Jesus, Peace be with him, as a merely historical personality, and Muslims
cease to see the Qur'an al-Karim as a mere artifact of early medieval
Arabian culture, but as the Word of God. This transformation of awareness
from the mundane to the sacred is accomplished by means of a recognition
of an ontological status for the Source of revelation, so that without the
metaphysical dimension of religion, the rest of it, including the salvific
potency of its symbols, the feelings of obligation to respect its
commandments, the attachment to participation in its rituals, all would
weaken and wither. [29]


The above discussion of postmodernism prepares the way
for a return to our original question about the relation of philosophy to
theology. Despite the fact that religious authorities might feel
threatened from time to time by questions that arise out of unfamiliar
philosophical discussions, many of whose participants are indeed hostile
toward religious authority, if not toward religion itself, ultimately the
theologian cannot escape an involvement with philosophy. Perhaps the most
persuasive reason we can offer to the theologian is that the philosophical
criticisms of religious ideas that plague the minds of the young require a
philosophical response if the young are to be guided.


Even if no amount of merely philosophical expertise
will be sufficient to remove doubt, some philosophical wisdom is necessary
in order to engage the sincere seeker in the spiritual work of rising
above the widespread Satanic suspicions that religion is little more than
a pack of lies. The presence of philosophical doubts in the minds of the
young was also the reason given by Allamah Tabataba i to Ayatullah
Burujerdi for publicly teaching philosophy in Qum. Philosophy presents
itself to theology as a servant without whose help the mess philosophy
herself has made cannot be cleaned up!


But there are other reasons for theology to graciously
accept the services offered by philosophy. Allah has graced the human mind
with a thirst for wisdom, and the wisdom sought includes knowledge of the
things of which religion speaks, as well as skill in practical evaluations
and the sort of precision in which logicians, mathematicians and
physicists take pride, and other things, such as history, as well. The
philosophical quest is one which propels the seeker to some degree of
understanding of all these areas and an attempt to fit them together. From
time to time philosophy might devote too much attention to a single
dimension of understanding, resulting in waves of logicism or empiricism
or historicism, but the structure of the human spirit ultimately cannot be
satisfied with a narrow slot from which to view reality.


I am told that Sohravardi Maqtul said that a person who
is not able to leave his body at will is not a real philosopher. I am not
sure what this means, but it suggests to me the philosophical need to
escape the confines of a physical perspective, the need to succumb to what
some have derided as "the transcendental temptation." [30]


Theology, on the other hand, is much more limited than
philosophy. The business of theology is not to offer a comprehensive
theory of reality, but merely to show that there is a Supreme Reality and
how this is related to lesser things. Without some attention to
philosophy, the business of theology is not likely to be very profitable,
because we do not get a very clear picture of God's relation to the world
unless we pay some attention to what the world is supposed to look like.
This does not mean that theology has to give an absolute stamp of approval
to some particular metaphysical speculation, but theologians should not
shy away from metaphysical issues either.


Theology is well served by philosophy if it interacts
with philosophical ideas without developing a dependency for a single
philosophical way of doing things. Philosophy, too, perhaps finds its true
vocation in service to theology. For if philosophy is to fulfill its goal
of providing an intelligible comprehensive synthesis, it must make room
for theological truth and knowledge of that truth, that is, by providing
for the needs of theology. This becomes the worship of philosophy, to be
at the service of theology; and as in all things human, the highest degree
of perfection is to be approached through worship of Allah, recognizing
one's own faqr before al-Ghani.


[1]. Plantinga's articles on this topic have not yet
been collected in the form of a book, but two anthologies in which there
are articles by him and discussions of his work are especially worth
mentioning: Robert Audi and William J. Wainwright, eds., Rationality,
Religious Belief, and Moral Commitment (Ithaca: Cornell University Press,
1986), and Alvin Plantinga and Nicholas Wolterstorff', eds., Faith and
Rationality: Reason and Belief in God (Notre Dame: University of Notre
Dame Press, 1983). Also worth mentioning is a book devoted to criticisms
of Plantinga's ideas and his responses: James E. Tomberlin and Peter Van
Inwagen, Alvin Plantinga, Profiles, Volume 5 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel,1985).


[2]. Plantinga's claim has been disputed by John
Beversluis, who argues that Calvin and the Reformed Church object to
natural theology for reason incompatible with the epistemological position
advocated by Plantinga. See John Beversluis, "Reforming the Reformed'
Objection to Natural Theology," Faith and Philosophy, 12:2, April 1995,
189-206.


[3]. See Rational Faith: Catholic Responses to Reformed
Epistemology, edited by Linda Zagzebski (Notre Dame: University of Notre
Dame Press, 1993).


[4]. His major work on this topic is Perceiving God:
The Epistemology of Religious Experience (Ithaca: Cornell University
Press, 1991).


[5]. See Michael C. Banner, The Justification of
Science and the Rationality of Religious Belief (Oxford: Oxford University
Press; 1992) and Nancey Murphy, Theology in the Age of Scientific
Reasoning (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1990).


[6]. Gary Gutting, Religious Belief and Religious
Skepticism (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1982).


[7]. Richard Swinburne, The Existence of God (London:
Oxford University Press, 1979).


[8]. John Hick, An Interpretation of Religion (New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1989).


[9]. Wayne Proudfoot, Religious Experience (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1985).


[10]. Steven Katz, ed., Mysticism and Philosophical
Analysis (New York: Oxford University Press, 1978).


[11]. Nelson Pike, Mystic Union: An Essay on the
Phenomenology of Mysticism (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1992).


[12]. Robert Cummings Neville, A TheologyPrimer
(Albany: SUNY, 1991).


[13]. See Thomas V Morris, The Logic of God Incarnate
(Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1986).


[14]. See Peter Geach, The Virtues (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1977), and Peter van Inwagen, "And Yet They
Are Not Three Gods But One God," in Thomas V Morris, ed., Philosophy and
the Christian Faith (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988),
pp. 241-278.


[15]. Robert Adams, A Modified Divine Command Theory
of Ethical Wrongness" in Louis Pojman, ed., Philosophy of Religion
(Belmont: Wadsworth Publishing Company, 1987), and "Divine Command
Metaethics Modified Again" The Journal of Religious Ethics 1:7, 91-97.


[16]. J. L. Mackie, The Miracle of Theism (New York:
Oxford University Press, 1982).


[17]. MacIntyre's most important books are After
Virtue, 2nd ed. (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984), Whose
Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press,
1988), and Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry: Encyclopedia, Geneology
and Tradition (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1990).
Translations of the first two of these works into Farsi are being
prepared, and a Farsi summary of After Virtue may be found in the journal
Ma'rifat, Nos. 9-18, and continuing.


[18]. See, for example, Eleonore Stump and Norman
Kretzmann, "Eternity" in Thomas V Morris, ed., The Concept ofGod (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1987).


[19]. See the articles in Linwood Urban and Douglas N.
Walton, eds., The Power of God (New York: Oxford University Press, 1978).


[20]. See William P Alston's, "Referring to God," in
his Divine Nature and Human Language: Essays in Philosophical Theology
(Ithaca: Comell University Press, 1989).


[21]. See D. Z. Phillips, Religion Without Explanation
(Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1976) and Norman -Malcolm, Wittgenstein: A
Religious Point of View? (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994).


[22]. See Gordon Kaufinan, "Evidentialism: A
Theologian's Response," Faith and Philosophy, 6:1 (January 1989), 35-46,
and the response by Eleonore Stump and Norman Kretzmann, "Theologically
Unfashionable Philosophy," Faith and Philosophy, 7:3 (July 1990), 329-339,
and the defense of Kaufinan's position by James A. Keller, "On the Issues
Dividing Contemporary Christian Philosophers and Theologians," Faith and
Philosophy, 10:1 (January 1993), 68-78 and James A. Keller, "Should
Christian Theologians become Christian Philosophers?" Faith and
Philosophy, 12:2 (April 1995), 260-268.


[23]. Jean-Francois Lyotard, tr. G. Bennington and B.
Massumi, The Postmodern Condition (Minneapolis: Minnesota University
Press, 1984).


[24]. His major work is Of Grammatology, tr. G. Spivak
(Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1974), but especially relevant
to contemporary Christian theology is Derrida and Negative Theology, ed.
Harold Coward and Toby Foshay (Albany: SUNY Press, 1992).


[25]. Georges Bataille, Theory of Religion, tr. R.
Hurley (New York: Zone Books, 1989).


[26]. Michel Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge,
ti. A. M. Sheridan-Snuth (New York: Harper & Row, 1972), also see the
biography, James Miller, The Passion of Michel Foucault (New York: Simon &
Schuster, 1993) in which the relation between Foucault's writings and his
sado-masochistic homosexuality is explored.


[27]. For a collection of essays in which postmodernist
thought is seen as offering resources for Christian theology see Faith and
Philosophy, Vol. 10, No. 4 (October 1993). 28. Postmodernism is also
starting to attract the attention of students of Islamic thought. See
Akbar S. Ahmed, Postmodernism and Islam: Predicament and Promise (London:
Routledge, 1992) and Ernest Gellner, Postmodernism, Reason and Religion
(London: Routledge,1992).


[29]. Worthy of note is Huston Smith's defense of the
religious world view over the postmodern proclamation (issued by Richard
Rorty) that "There is no Big Picture:" "Postmodernism and the World's
Religions" in The Truth about Truth, ed., Walter Truett Anderson (Los
Angeles: Jeremey P Tarcher, 1995), an address originally delivered in
Kuala Lumpur for a symposium on "Islam and the Challenge of Modernity,"
and later revised without references to Islam as "The Religious
Significance of Postmodernism: A Rejoinder" in Faith and Philosophy 12:3
(July 1995), 409-422.


[30]. See the defense of atheistic skepticism by Paul
Kurtz, The Transcendental Temptation (New York: Prometheus, 1986).


/ 4