MODERN PHILOSOPHY [Electronic resources] نسخه متنی

اینجــــا یک کتابخانه دیجیتالی است

با بیش از 100000 منبع الکترونیکی رایگان به زبان فارسی ، عربی و انگلیسی

MODERN PHILOSOPHY [Electronic resources] - نسخه متنی

| نمايش فراداده ، افزودن یک نقد و بررسی
افزودن به کتابخانه شخصی
ارسال به دوستان
جستجو در متن کتاب
بیشتر
تنظیمات قلم

فونت

اندازه قلم

+ - پیش فرض

حالت نمایش

روز نیمروز شب
جستجو در لغت نامه
بیشتر
لیست موضوعات
توضیحات
افزودن یادداشت جدید




What Is Wrong With Kant's
Philosophy?


Introduction


David Hume
(1711-1776), native of Edinburgh and a product of its
university, denied the existence of all substantial reality, material or
spiritual. In his Treatise on Human Nature he declares that man's mind
is only a collection of perceptions. These perceptions are either impressions
or ideas. Impressions are sensations of pleasure, pain, awareness of
qualities and relations. Ideas are but the faintly remembered images of
impressions formerly experienced. This vague philosophy has a very modern
sound: a collection of impressions collected nowhere; contents of a mind
which is not a container. Here we have the smug unintelligibility of the
modern neo-realist's definition of mind as "a cross-section of the
environment." Hume holds that the only thing that can be said, with full
certainty, to exist is our perceptions (impressions and ideas). In and among
these perceptions there is no causal connection; indeed, there is no knowable
causality anywhere. If things outside us really do exist, there is no proof of
their existence available to us.


Kant Comes Out of His "Dogmatic Slumber"


Over
in Germany, in his native city of Koenigsberg, a professor named Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) read Hume's argument
with dismay, and finally tossed them aside as "dogmatic dreams." Hume
takes away all grounds of certitude; the best a man might have of him is a thin
probability, and this, as Kant noticed, is not usable knowledge at all. What a
man needs, said Kant, and what he can have is truly scientific knowledge,
that is, knowledge that is universally and necessarily true and reliable.


The
experiences of the senses is individual, and, no matter how consistently and
for how long a time the senses find a fact solid, there is always the
possibility that the next experience will show it to vary. So far Kant agrees
with Hume: sense-experience cannot give the mind more than probability. But,
said Kant, there is another element in knowledge, an a priori and subjective
element which is anterior to sense-experience and in no wise dependent on it.
This is the element which enables us to have true and certain knowledge and to
add item to item with complete security in building up the edifice of science.


We
pause here to settle the meaning of important terms. Knowledge that we obtain
through experience is a posteriori knowledge, that is, it comes after
experience and is dependent upon it. Now, it is the Aristotelian, Thomistic, Scholastic, and Contextual Realist doctrine that
all human knowledge is of this type; no knowledge is born in us; no item
of knowledge exists in man except such as has been acquired.


Kant,
however, insisted on the existence of certain "forms" or items of
knowledge (space and time, certain regulative judgments, and certain master-ideas)
as inborn and a priori. Of course, there is a legitimate use of the
terms a priori and a posteriori (literally "from
beforehand" and "from afterwards") in describing types of
argument. But there is no legitimate use of a priori as a term descriptive
of knowledge itself. Kant uses the term so, and he follows the despised Hume so
far as to make the knowledge described by this term a very part of the mind of
man, an element of its being and not merely an element of its equipment.


To
answer the basic question, "What can I know with scientific
certitude?" Kant wrote his book The Critique of Pure Reason. In
this work, Kant assigns to man a threefold knowing-power: sensibility,
intellect, reason. Knowable things, on the other hand, are of two classes:
appearances of things or phenomena, and essences of things or noumena. Man, by sensibility (that is, by his
senses) takes in the phenomena of the world about him. Somehow, we know not
how, the phenomena set his sense-power to work; we dare not say that the senses
perceive even the phenomena as these exist in nature; we may only say that
somehow phenomena stir the senses to act.


Now
the formal constituent, the essential element, of the sensing-power or
sensibility (that is, its character or "shape") is the twofold
determination of space-and-time. Man has sense-experiences
"here" and "now," and he recalls them as "there"
and "then." But this conditioning of phenomena by space and time
is man's own contribution to the knowledge-act. Space and time in no wise represent
things, nor are they things; they are the inborn a priori element of the
sensing-power. Just as a curiously shaped bottle will take in liquid or powder
and conform the mass of the substance taken in to its own shape, so the
sensing-power, which has the shape of space-and-time, takes in the
action of phenomena on the senses and shapes these phenomena accordingly. The
result (that is, phenomena-conditioned-by-space-and-time) is called empirical
intuition.


Now,
just as phenomena stir the sensibility to act, so the finished products of
sensation (that is, empirical intuitions) stir the next knowing power, the
intellect, to act. The intellect takes in the empirical intuitions and
conforms them to its shape, its own inborn a priori forms. These
forms are four sets of triple judgments, called the twelve categories.
These are like grooves or molds into which the molten metal of empirical
intuitions is poured, and the resultant piece of knowledge is, in each case, a judgment.


The
four master categories (each of which has three branches) are: quantity,
quality, relation, and modality. Thus the judgment "A comes from B as
effect from cause" is not the objective knowing by the mind of a state of
fact; it is merely the result of the action of intellect turning the
sense-findings (or empirical intuitions) of A and B through the groove (or
category) of relation, and through that branch of relation called cause-effect.


Once
more, just as the finished products of sensibility (that is, empirical
intuitions) stir the intellect to the act of judging, so the judgments of the
intellect stir the reason to its action. The innate a priori
shape of reason is determined by three master-ideas: the idea of the
self, the idea of the no-self, the idea of the super-self. In
other words, the three regulative ideas of reason are the ideas of self, the
world, and God. The judgments of intellect are poured through the threefold
mold of reason, and the result is reasoned knowledge.


Now,
the essential thing about knowledge, when we attempt to fix its value on the
score of truth and certitude, centers in judgments. After all, reason
merely handles judgments and learns from them. Upon judgments we must fix our
attention. There are two types of judgment, a priori and a posteriori.
Looked at in another way, there are two other types: synthetic and analytic.
We already know the meaning of a priori and a posteriori, and
indeed, according to Kant, all judgments are a priori. We must look at
the other terms.


A
judgment is rightly called synthetic when it is "put
together," for that is precisely what the word synthetic means. If
I make the judgment, "John is sick," I have a synthetic judgment; the
predicate does not necessarily belong to the subject, but I put it with
the subject because I have learned from John or from his doctor that it happens
to belong there. But if I make the judgment, "A circle is round," I
have an analytic judgment; for by analyzing the subject, by studying it
and knowing just what it is, I learn that the predicate used belongs there,
since a circle to be a circle must be round.


Kant
held that the only judgment which can give absolute certitude must be a
priori, since, indeed, he admits no other type. But, he maintains, an a
priori judgment that is analytic marks no advance in knowledge. To
build up science, there must be growth, development, advancement. Hence there
must be synthetic judgments which are also a prior.


The synthetic a priori judgment may be called
the heart of Kant's philosophy. And we may say now in passing that the
synthetic a priori judgment is a contradiction in terms and in thought; it is
an impossibility.


The
examples offered by Kant are either (in our terminology) a posteriori
judgments, or they are analytic judgments. For instance, Kant says that
the judgment "five plus seven equals twelve" is a synthetic a
priori judgment. It is nothing of the kind.
It is a simple analytic judgment.
Replace the words or the figures for five and seven and twelve by an equivalent
number of dots or strokes; you will have exactly the same thing on either side
of the equals-mark. The judgment is as plainly analytic as "A is A."


Let us
cast back a moment, and make a summing up of the Kantian theory of human
knowing:

  • Phenomena of bodily things
    somehow stir man's sensibility to action, and sense takes in phenomena in
    its own way, shaping and conditioning them by its innate forms of
    space-and-time, thus producing empirical intuitions.

  • The empirical intuitions
    somehow stir man's intellect to take them in and run them through its
    forms or categories, thus producing judgments, the truly certain and
    valuable judgment always being synthetic a priori.

  • Finally, the judgments of
    intellect somehow stir the reason to take them in and view them in the
    light of its regulative ideas of self, the world, and God.


  • Notice
    that the sole point of connection of man's knowledge with reality outside the
    mind is the vague influence of phenomena on the sensing-power. From that point
    on, the whole process of knowing, and its products, are man's own. Here is idealism, here is subjectivism
    with a vengeance. And Kant plainly asserts that the noumena
    or essences of things cannot be known by man. The phenomenon is not strictly
    knowable, but it moves the sense to act; the noumenon
    is not knowable at all. The noumenon (Das Ding an sich)
    lies outside the reach of mortal man.


    So
    Kant is as subjectivistic
    as Hume ever dared be. And yet this is the man who threw Hume's book aside with
    the sneer, "Dogmatic dreams!" What singular smugness could have made
    Kant suppose that he was dealing with the problem of knowledge critically
    and not dogmatically? Yet he calls his system "transcendental
    criticism."


    Metaphysics Becomes Impossible


    Since
    we cannot know noumena, the science of metaphysics,
    the very heart of philosophy as the Greeks and Scholastics and other followers
    of the Perennial Philosophy understand it, becomes illusory and impossible.


    Is it not strange that a man of Kant's
    undoubted intellectual gifts did not notice here an absurd contradiction? Why,
    he has just finished explaining to us, in great detail, the whole nature of the
    human mind; and now he concludes that we cannot know the nature of anything!


    And
    his reasoning about the character of the mind, and about the nature of
    phenomena and noumena, is actually interwoven with
    terms and thoughts metaphysical; yet he says that metaphysics is illusory
    and impossible!


    So
    much for Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. It will be noticed that the
    doctrine contained in this work opens the way to complete
    skepticism, and therewith it opens the way to a denial of moral
    obligation and of purpose in human existence. For if nothing can be known with
    certitude, as skepticism maintains, then there are no certainties in the realm
    of morals, religion, or social duties; then there is no certainty that man is
    made for a purpose at all, or even that man exists.


    Whether
    Kant noticed this fact, and, as a Lutheran, deplored it, or whether (as has
    been said) his Emperor summoned him and demanded that he furnish a
    philosophical basis for morals and religion, cannot be said. But Kant wrote a
    second book, The Critique of Practical Reason, to supply the defect
    mentioned.


    The Critique of Practical Reason


    Kant
    said that pure reason is not enough for man; he must live by practical
    reason as well. In his first book, Kant sought the answer to the question,
    "What can man know with certitude?" The answer was, "He can have
    true certitude by his synthetic a priori judgments." But this is
    mere statement. The real answer to which Kant's work inclines the thinking mind
    is, "Man can know nothing with
    certitude."


    Kant's
    second book, The Critique of Practical Reason, answered the question,
    "Are there certitudes, outside the reach of pure reason, that I must
    recognize and act upon?" Kant answers with an emphatic, There are." These
    truths are known with certitude by practical reason. First, a man is
    aware of duty. He knows with clear certitude that murder and stealing
    are wrong, and that he has the indispensable duty of avoiding such things. He
    knows that there are certain loyalties which indicate things that he is in duty
    bound to observe and do. By his practical reason, man is aware of the inner
    command, "Thou shalt" and "Thou shalt not." This command is categorical, that
    is, it is unconditional; it is not, "Do this, if you please,"
    "Avoid that when convenient"; it is a matter of simple "Do"
    and "Avoid." Kant calls this inner voice The Categorical
    Imperative.


    A
    Christian would call it conscience, and would explain that it is the voice of
    reason (the same reason with which we work out a theorem in geometry)
    pronouncing on the agreement or disagreement of a situation (here and now to be
    decided) with the norm or law of morality. Kant's Categorical Imperative
    is like conscience in its clear decision and unequivocal command; it is entirely
    unlike conscience in its blindly unreasoning assumption of authority.


    First,
    then, man's awareness of duty is a certitude; it is a certitude because of The
    Categorical Imperative. Now, this Categorical Imperative is a law. But a
    law must come from a lawmaker. Neither I myself have set up my Categorical
    Imperative (for it often orders me to do what I should like to avoid, and to
    shun what I would willingly do) nor has it come from any earthly king, court,
    or senate, for it speaks with an authority that is absolute and not one
    supported by temporal sanctions of fine or imprisonment. It is a supreme law;
    it is an absolute law. It must come then from the Supreme and Absolute Being.
    That is, it must come from God. Therefore, God exists.


    Further,
    the Categorical Imperative makes a man aware, not only of duty, but of the fact
    that he must freely embrace the performance of duty. He is aware that he can
    disregard, although he cannot be ignorant of, this law of conduct. In a word,
    he is aware, and with true certitude, that he is a free and responsible
    being.


    Again,
    man, a free and responsible being, is aware that by freely acting in accordance
    with the commands of the Categorical Imperative he perfects himself. And
    he is aware that this self-perfecting may go on through the longest life
    without reaching the limits of its capability. Therefore, he concludes, he can
    go on becoming more and more perfect forever. In other words, man is
    aware of endless existence before him; he knows he has an immortal soul.
    Thus out of the cunning device of The Categorical Imperative Kant draws
    the doctrines that satisfy his Lutheranism (or his Emperor), although his basic
    philosophy of "transcendental criticism" knows nothing of these
    doctrines. He sets forth, in orthodox fashion, the practical truths of
    the existence of God, the fact of moral duty, the immortality of the soul, the
    freedom of the human will.


    Note:
    Kant wrote a third book, The Critique of Aesthetic Judgment, in which he
    brings out the attractiveness of moral goodness in a manner more striking than
    that of The Critique of Practical Reason.


    Despite errors, absurdities, and
    contradictions, Kant's philosophy -- notably that of The Critique of Pure
    Reason
    -- has exercised a tremendous influence upon human thinking for
    almost two centuries.


    It
    exhibits the roots of those weaknesses we have come to regard as characteristic
    of what is loosely called "the German philosophy."
    It refuses to face reality (witness the wholly subjectivistic character of knowledge);
    It unduly stresses the ego (witness the inner and
    autonomous character of knowledge and morality);
    It proclaims the
    perfectibility of the will, upon which the followers of Kant were soon to harp
    most strongly -- and from Nietzsche to Hitler we are to hear of "the
    will to power," the will which makes "the superman" and
    "the master race."


    A Final Word on Kant


    In
    offering and defending his low estimate of pure reason as incapable of
    achieving certitude (apart from the mysterious judgments which are synthetic
    a priori
    ) Kant appeals to his so-called "antinomies" or
    "contradictions." He holds that when pure reason tries to apply the
    categories in the abstract realm of logical inference (whereas its business is
    to pour findings through fixed molds) it gets beyond itself and comes a
    cropper. It finds that it can prove, with equal facility, things directly
    opposed. Thus, he says, it can prove that space is finite, and also infinite;
    it can prove matter divisible and indivisible; it can prove human freedom
    existent and nonexistent; it can prove that God is necessary and also
    non-necessary.


    In all this, and in the examples offered in
    proof of it, Kant is entirely gratuitous and sophistical. Besides, he stands
    self-condemned in using logical reasoning to establish the fact that logical reasoning
    is useless.


    We
    merely mention the "antinomies" because we discern in them an element
    of materialism in the heart of an idealistic theory. This
    materialism was to appear in full form in later philosophies which took
    inspiration, at least in part, from the doctrines of Immanuel Kant.


    Kant's
    philosophy is fundamentally wrong and is one of the major contributors to the
    intellectual insanity which we see today.


    / 30